HOPE OVER EXPERIENCE II
In
a recent article in Slate (“Save the Allegory!"), Laura Miller makes a plea for deploying
the word allegory correctly in cultural criticism—in essence, contradicting the
recent tendency to call an “allegory” any film or book that can be interpreted
as a commentary on society or politics. As
she argues, allegory is not accidental, it is generative of the work; and
allegorical figures in literature are generally called out as such (Fortitude,
or Poliphilo—‘Lover of All Things’). She rightly reclaims allegory’s medieval
past, but here the deployment of the word “medieval” to describe anything
before the “modern” era is also problematic (but I’m not a fan either of
calling sixteenth-century art or literature “Early Modern”). The Middle Ages
were the middle centuries between the classical culture of antiquity and its
rebirth in the Renaissance. That may be a construct, but it’s a useful one, far
more coherent than folding the Renaissance and Baroque into the trajectory of
Modernism. Spenser’s The Faerie Queene
is not a medieval book, but neither is the Hypnerotomachia
Poliphili, written a century earlier (when Italy was fully in the
Renaissance while England, perhaps, did in fact remain “medieval”). This is not
to say, at the same time, that the Middle Ages were disconnected from
antiquity, nor that they weren’t prescient of the Renaissance (witness Dante):
see the still classic The Survival of the Pagan Gods by Jean Seznec.
The Triumph of Hope Over Experience
A version of an allegory that, this time,
implies some irony in Hope’s gestures:
she attempts to light an altar pyre,
but the green kindling generates smoke;
she pours water onto a dead tree stump;
her temples are greying
|
But
I’m especially interested in allegory in the visual arts, and in the wider
culture of the Renaissance and Baroque (like opera, for example). I’m interested in it because it was formative
for that culture, but also because my interest in recovering the tools of that
culture means that I actually practice
it. In practicing allegory I’ve marginalized myself not only with respect to
mainstream modernist culture, but also with the ascendant neo-Realist
phenomenon (which I just can’t accept calling “Classical Realism”). It’s a
marginal position because much of Modernism was predicated on the abolition of
allegory, beginning with literature; the Realist painter Courbet drove a stake
through its heart in the nineteenth century in the visual arts (even if
academic artists continued to practice an enfeebled version of it into the
early twentieth century). Both modernists and realists are still suspicious of,
if not opposed to, allegory. Perhaps, in the latter case, rightly
enough—there’s no stranger iteration of allegory than the one populated by ordinary,
realist (rather than idealized) figures.
For
me, the critical thing is that allegory was not baggage appended to painting or
sculpture in the seventeenth century: it was formative, essential, causal. It
was not foisted on artists by pretentious patrons; instead, it was how artists themselves
thought and how they perceived the world. When the great Gianlorenzo Bernini
was in the midst of a brief period of being marginalized himself, he set to
work on an allegorical sculpture, Truth
Revealed by Time, both to comfort himself and to make an argument to his
marginalizers. Even his seemingly intimate and “realist” portrait of his lover
Costanza Buonarelli has been recently interpreted in, if not allegorical terms, at least
rhetorical ones.
Now,
mythologies can be interpreted allegorically without being intended as such—the
hero’s journey, the battle with brute nature, the overcoming of labors. These
can be credible allegorical readings because even in antiquity the myths were
understood to be messages (maybe not in Homer’s day, but certainly by Ovid’s). But
while Plutarch’s Lives may also
contain messages about exemplary behavior, the real people he describes are not
symbols or types, not gods or mythical heroes, but specific, individual
characters. They cannot take on the burden of allegories because they cannot
transcend their individual characteristics and stories—which Plutarch is at
pains to narrate as realistically as possible.
the design for The Triumph of Hope |
The
taste for allegory may not accord with our dominant zeitgeist: too ancien régime, too abstruse or pretentious,
too opaque. But it’s also not real enough for most people, doesn’t dazzle with
its meticulous, every-hair-on-the-head depictions. Its imagery is broad,
general, “classical.” At the same time, it’s not divorced from the depiction of
reality; some of the greatest allegorical painters were quite fine
portraitists. Sargent felt something of this need to distinguish his late-career
allegories in the Boston Museum of Fine Arts from his virtuoso portraiture; but
for my money he went too far in the other direction, his allegories lacking any
sense of the sensual, tactile, and human that suffuse the rest of his oeuvre:
they are more graphics, almost abstractions, than paintings. That taste that
distinguishes realism from classicism also distinguishes classicism from
abstraction. And what distinguishes ars
from scientia is judgment, formed by
experience of the beautiful, which is found more on canvas and marble than
flesh and blood.
No comments:
Post a Comment